This symposium addresses many similarly troubling judicial actions that add up to an entrenched pattern of government by judges that is nothing less than the usurpation of politics. The question here explored, in full awareness of its far-reaching consequences, is whether we have reached or are reaching the point where conscientious citizens can no longer give moral assent to the existing regime.
Americans are not accustomed to speaking of a regime. Regimes are what other nations have. The American tradition abhors the notion of the rulers and the ruled. We do not live under a government, never mind under a regime; we are the government. The traditions of democratic self-governance are powerful in our civics textbooks and in popular consciousness. This symposium asks whether we may be deceiving ourselves and, if we are, what are the implications of that self- deception. By the word "regime" we mean the actual, existing system of government. The question that is the title of this symposium is in no way hyperbolic. The subject before us is the end of democracy.
Since the defeat of communism, some have spoken of the end of history. By that they mean, inter alia, that the great controversies about the best form of governance are over: there is no alternative to democracy. Perhaps that, too, is wishful thinking and self-deception. Perhaps the United States, for so long the primary bearer of the democratic idea, has itself betrayed that idea and become something else. If so, the chief evidence of that betrayal is the judicial usurpation of politics.
Politics, Aristotle teaches, is free persons deliberating the question, How ought we to order our life together? Democratic politics means that "the people" deliberate and decide that question. In the American constitutional order the people do that through debate, elections, and representative political institutions. But is that true today? Has it been true for, say, the last fifty years? Is it not in fact the judiciary that deliberates and answers the really important questions entailed in the question, How ought we to order our life together? Again and again, questions that are properly political are legalized, and even speciously constitutionalized. This symposium is an urgent call for the repoliticizing of the American regime. Some of the authors fear the call may come too late.
The emergence of democratic theory and practice has a long and complicated history, and one can cite many crucial turning points. One such is the 1604 declaration of Parliament to James I: "The voice of the people, in the things of their knowledge, is as the voice of God." We hold that only the voice of God is to be treated as the voice of God, but with respect to political sovereignty that declaration is a keystone of democratic government. Washington, Madison, Adams, Franklin, Jefferson, and the other founders were adamant about the competence- meaning both the authority and capacity-of the people to govern themselves. They had no illusions that the people would always decide rightly, but they would not invest the power to decide in a ruling elite. The democracy they devised was a republican system of limited government, with checks and balances, including judicial review, and representative means for the expression of the voice of the people. But always the principle was clear: legitimate government is government by the consent of the governed. The founders called this order an experiment, and it is in the nature of experiments that they can fail.
The questions addressed have venerable precedent. The American experiment intended to remedy the abuses of an earlier regime. The Declaration of Independence was not addressed to "light and transient causes" or occasional "evils [that] are sufferable." Rather, it says: "But when a long train of abuses and usurpations, pursuing invariably the same Object evinces a design to reduce them under absolute Despotism, it is their right, it is their duty, to throw off such Government and to provide new Guards for their future security." The following essays are certain about the "long train of abuses and usurpations," and about the prospect-some might say the present reality- of despotism. Like our authors, we are much less certain about what can or should be done about it.
The proposition examined in the following articles is this: The government of the United States of America no longer governs by the consent of the governed. With respect to the American people, the judiciary has in effect declared that the most important questions about how we ought to order our life together are outside the purview of "things of their knowledge." Not that judges necessarily claim greater knowledge; they simply claim, and exercise, the power to decide. The citizens of this democratic republic are deemed to lack the competence for self-government. The Supreme Court itself-notably in the Casey decision of 1992-has raised the alarm about the legitimacy of law in the present regime. Its proposed solution is that citizens should defer to the decisions of the Court. Our authors do not consent to that solution. The twelfth Chief Justice of the Supreme Court, Harlan Fiske Stone (1872-1946), expressed his anxiety: "While unconstitutional exercise of power by the executive or legislative branches of the Government is subject to judicial restraint, the only check upon our own exercise of power is our own sense of restraint." The courts have not, and perhaps cannot, restrain themselves, and it may be that in the present regime no other effective restraints are available. If so, we are witnessing the end of democracy.
As important as democracy is, the symposium addresses another question still more sobering. Law, as it is presently made by the judiciary, has declared its independence from morality. Indeed, as explained below, morality-especially traditional morality, and most especially morality associated with religion-has been declared legally suspect and a threat to the public order. Among the most elementary principles of Western Civilization is the truth that laws which violate the moral law are null and void and must in conscience be disobeyed. In the past and at present, this principle has been invoked, on both the right and the left, by those who are frequently viewed as extremists. It was, however, the principle invoked by the founders of this nation. It was the principle invoked by the antislavery movement and, more recently, by Martin Luther King, Jr. It is the principle invoked today by, among many others, Pope John Paul II.
In this connection, Professor Robert George of Princeton explores the significance of the encyclical Evangelium Vitae (The Gospel of Life). Addressing laws made also by our courts, the Pope declares, "Laws and decrees enacted in contravention of the moral order, and hence of the divine will, can have no binding force in conscience. . . . Indeed such laws undermine the very nature of authority and result in shameful abuse." We would only add to Professor George's brilliant analysis that the footnotes to that section of Evangelium Vitae refer to the 1937 encyclical of Pius XI, Mit Brennender Sorge (With Burning Concern) and other papal statements condemning the crimes of Nazi Germany. America is not and, please God, will never become Nazi Germany, but it is only blind hubris that denies it can happen here and, in peculiarly American ways, may be happening here.
We are prepared for the charge that publishing this symposium is irresponsibly provocative and even alarmist. Again, it is the Supreme Court that has raised the question of the legitimacy of its law, and we do not believe the Pope is an alarmist. We expect there will be others who, even if they agree with the analysis of the present system, will respond, So what? Unmoved by the prospect of the end of democracy, and skeptical about the existence of a moral law, they might say that the system still "works" to the satisfaction of the great majority and, niceties about moral legitimacy aside, we will muddle through so long as that continues to be the case. That, we believe, is a recklessly myopic response to our present circumstance.
Some of our authors examine possible responses to laws that cannot be obeyed by conscientious citizens-ranging from noncompliance to resistance to civil disobedience to morally justified revolution. The purpose of the symposium is not to advocate these or other steps; it is an attempt to understand where the existing system may be leading us. But we need not confine ourselves to speculating about what might happen in the future. What is happening now is more than disturbing enough. What is happening now is a growing alienation of millions of Americans from a government they do not recognize as theirs; what is happening now is an erosion of moral adherence to this political system.
What are the consequences when many millions of children are told and come to believe that the government that rules them is morally illegitimate? Many of us have not been listening to what is more and more frequently being said by persons of influence and moral authority. Many examples might be cited. Supreme Court Justice Antonin Scalia in a recent lecture: "A Christian should not support a government that suppresses the faith or one that sanctions the taking of an innocent human life." The Archbishop of Denver in a pastoral letter on recent court rulings: "The direction of the modern state is against the dignity of human life. These decisions harbinger a dramatic intensifying of the conflict between the Catholic Church and governing civil authorities."
Professor Hittinger observes that the present system "has made what used to be the most loyal citizens-religious believers-enemies of the common good whenever their convictions touch upon public things." The American people are incorrigibly, however confusedly, religious. Tocqueville said religion is "the first political institution" of American democracy because it was through religion that Americans are schooled in morality, the rule of law, and the habits of public duty. What happens to the rule of law when law is divorced from, indeed pitted against, the first political institution?
"God and country" is a motto that has in the past come easily, some would say too easily, to almost all Americans. What are the cultural and political consequences when many more Americans, perhaps even a majority, come to the conclusion that the question is "God or country"? What happens not in "normal" times, when maybe America can muddle along, but in a time of great economic crisis, or in a time of war when the youth of another generation are asked to risk their lives for their country? We do not know what would happen then, and we hope never to find out.
What is happening now is the displacement of a constitutional order by a regime that does not have, will not obtain, and cannot command the consent of the people. If enough people do not care or do not know, that can be construed as a kind of negative consent, but it is not what the American people were taught to call government by the consent of the governed. We hope that more people know and more people care than is commonly supposed, and that it is not too late for effective recourse to whatever remedies may be available. It is in the service of that hope that we publish this symposium.
Most members of the Court seem to be gnostics, firmly believing they
have access to wisdom denied the rest of us. "What secret knowledge, one
must wonder, is breathed into lawyers when they become Justices of this
Court?" Scalia has asked. "Day by day, case by case, [the Court] is busy
designing a Constitution for a country I do not recognize."
This last term was unusually rich in examples. The Court moved a long
way toward making homosexual conduct a constitutional right, adopted the
radical feminist view that men and women are essentially identical,
continued to view the First Amendment as a protection of self-
gratification rather than of the free articulation of ideas, and
overturned two hundred years of history to hold that political patronage
is unconstitutional.
A few cities in Colorado, reflecting the political influence of
homosexuals, had in recent years enacted ordinances prohibiting
discrimination on grounds of sexual orientation. Even private persons
who believe strongly that homosexual conduct is immoral or prohibited by
religion were forbidden to act on those beliefs. A person with a room to
rent, for example, could not turn away a homosexual couple. In a
statewide referendum Coloradans adopted a constitutional provision,
Amendment 2, which precluded local governments from adopting such
provisions. The Supreme Court, in an indecipherable opinion (Romer
v. Evans), held that this denial of special status to homosexuals
violated the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The
theory, apparently, was that homosexuals were impermissibly burdened if
they had to secure special protection, equivalent to that afforded
racial minorities, at the state rather than the local level. The law
could be explained, the Court said, only by animosity toward
homosexuals. The opinion closed with the preposterous assertion that
"Amendment 2 classifies homosexuals not to further a proper legislative
end but to make them unequal to everyone else."
To the contrary, any constitutional provision does what Amendment 2 did-
it removes from some groups the capacity to alter the law except at the
state or federal level. If one took the majority's assertions seriously,
as Scalia's dissent noted, state constitutional provisions prohibiting
polygamy would violate the equal protection principle. The State of
Utah, for example, was admitted to the Union only on condition that its
constitution's prohibition of polygamy could not be revoked without the
consent of the United States-thus requiring polygamists to persuade the
entire nation and not simply the voters of Utah. Matters are even worse
than that, however. Under what appears to be the majority's rationale,
it is difficult to see how any federal or state statute could be
constitutional. Persons adversely affected by any national or
state law are by definition unable to get relief at the local level. If
homosexuals in Colorado were unfairly burdened by Amendment 2, then we
are all unfairly burdened by the very existence of federal and state
law.
The majority did not even mention the ten-year-old decision in
Bowers v. Hardwick, which had held, in keeping with long-
standing constitutional understanding, that a state may make homosexual
conduct a criminal offense. Since the Court has now held that the denial
of special status to homosexuals is unconstitutional, Bowers
must be taken to have been silently overruled.
Romer is a prime instance of "constitutional law" made by
sentiment having nothing to do with the Constitution. What can explain
the Court majority's decision? Only the newly faddish approval of
homosexual conduct among the elite classes from which the Justices come
and to which most of them respond. We are on our way to the approval of
homosexual conduct, despite the moral objections of most Americans,
because the Court views such moral disapproval as nothing more than
redneck bigotry.
The cultural elite have more fads than one, however. Radical feminism
overrode the Constitution in United States v. Virginia, which
held, seven votes to one, that the equal protection clause required
Virginia Military Institute to admit women. VMI had been an all-male
military college for over 150 years and had coexisted peaceably with the
said equal protection clause for 128 of those years. The historic
understanding was that such single-sex schools were fully consistent
with the Constitution. VMI provided "adversative methods" of training,
which meant a program that was extremely rigorous mentally, physically,
and emotionally. The admission of women will change the nature of the
institution; women will not get what they supposedly sought: VMI
training. Only sterile feminist logic could lead anyone to imagine that
there are no inherent differences between men and women in these
matters.
Once again, Justice Scalia (Justice Thomas took no part because his son
attends The Citadel, another all-male military college) destroyed the
majority opinion. "Much of the Court's opinion is devoted to deprecating
the close-mindedness of our forbears with regard to women's education,
and even with regard to the treatment of women in areas that have
nothing to do with education. . . . The virtue of a democratic system
with a First Amendment is that it readily enables the people, over time,
to be persuaded that what they took for granted is not so, and to change
their laws accordingly. That system is destroyed if the smug assurances
of each age are removed from the democratic process and written into the
Constitution. So to counterbalance the Court's criticism of our
ancestors, let me say a word in their praise: they left us free to
change. The same cannot be said of this most illiberal Court, which has
embarked on a course of inscribing one after another of the current
preferences of the society (and in some cases only the counter-
majoritarian preferences of the society's law-trained elite) into our
Basic Law."
Scalia understates how radical an antidemocratic course the Court has
taken. The Justices are not inscribing current preferences of our
society into the Constitution, for those preferences can be easily
placed in statutes by legislatures. When the Court declares a statute
unconstitutional it overrides current popular desires. The
counter-majoritarian preferences are not simply those of a law-trained
elite, but those of a wider cultural elite that includes journalists,
academics, entertainers, and the like. If only a law-trained elite were
involved, the Court could not do what it is doing.
Also during this past term, the Court majority struck down, on First
Amendment grounds, a federal statute which required cable television
operators who leased access to channels to others to segregate on a
single channel "patently offensive" depictions of sexual activities or
organs. The operator had to block that channel from viewer access and to
unblock it only upon a subscriber's written request. The Court found
this speech-restrictive, continuing its transformation of the First
Amendment as a guarantee of the free exchange of ideas to a guarantee of
individual self-gratification.
In a pair of cases, the Court found that normal patronage by government
violated, of all things, the First Amendment. A company was removed from
the list of available companies to perform towing services for a city,
allegedly because the owner had supported the mayor's opponent in a
reelection campaign. Another city terminated a trash hauler's at-will
contract, allegedly because the hauler had been an outspoken critic of
the Board of County Commissioners. Such practices are as old as the
nation and are regulated by innumerable statutes, but the Court suddenly
elevated patronage to the level of a First Amendment violation.
Not one of these five decisions bears any resemblance to the actual
Constitution. There is no question of a mistake being made. The Justices
know full well what they are doing, which means that Scalia and Thomas
are right: a majority of Justices have decided to rule us without any
warrant in law. If there is an "actual" Constitution it can only be the
set of principles those who made the Constitution law understood
themselves to be ordaining.
The idea that the Constitution should be interpreted according to that
original understanding has been made to seem an extreme position. That
is convenient for those who want results democracy will not give them,
but the truth is that violation of original understanding ought to be
the extreme position. Would it be legitimate for a judge in the United
Kingdom, which has no constitution comparable to ours, to strike down an
act of Parliament on the ground he did not like it? Obviously not. But a
U.S. judge who goes beyond the Constitution behaves like the
hypothetical U.K. judge. Democratic theory requires that a judge set the
majority's desires at naught only in accordance with a superior law-in
our case, the written Constitution. A judge who departs from the
Constitution, as the majority did in the five cases mentioned, is
applying no law other than his will. Our country is being radically
altered, step by step, by Justices who are not following any law.
This is not entirely new. During the nineteenth century, the Court often
made up its own Constitution, most notoriously in the 1857 decision in
Dred Scott v. Sandford. Chief Justice Roger Taney's opinion for
the Court found a constitutional right, good against the federal
government, to own slaves. But it wasn't until this century, when the
Court invented the theory that the Bill of Rights limited states as well
as the federal government, that the opportunities for judicial
government exploded. The First Amendment speech clause has been made a
guarantor of moral chaos, while its religion clauses have been reshaped
to banish religious symbolism from public life. The Court invented a
right of privacy and used it to create a wholly specious right to
abortion. The list of such incursions into the legitimate sphere of
democratic control goes on and on.
Lower courts, state and federal, catch the fever. Hawaii's Supreme Court
is about to make marriage between homosexuals a constitutional right.
Connecticut's court has ruled that racial imbalance in public schools
violates the state constitution even though the imbalance is a result of
residential patterns and not the product of any government action. Two
federal courts of appeals have invented a constitutional right to
assisted suicide, and one court is apparently willing to extend the
right to euthanasia. God knows what will come next.
On the evidence, we must conclude, I think, that this tendency of
courts, including the Supreme Court, is the inevitable result of our
written Constitution and the power of judicial review. Even in the
depths of the Warren Court era some of us thought that the Court's
performance, though profoundly illegitimate, could be brought within the
range of the minimally acceptable by logical persuasion or the
appointment of more responsible judges, or both. We now know that was an
illusion. A Court majority is impervious to arguments about its proper
behavior. It seems safe to say that, as our institutional arrangements
now stand, the Court can never be made a legitimate element of a
basically democratic polity.
Republican Presidents have used the nomination process in an effort to
change the direction of the Court with almost zero results on the major
issues. After twelve years of Presidents Reagan and Bush, each of whom
made a determined effort to appoint Justices who would abide by the
Constitution as originally understood, we seem farther than ever from a
restrained Court. Between them, Reagan and Bush had five appointments.
Only two try to relate their decisions to the Constitution as the men
who wrote, proposed, and ratified it understood it. A majority of the
Justices has become more arrogantly authoritarian than ever.
The illegitimacy of the Court's departures from the Constitution is
underscored by the fact that no Justice has ever attempted a
justification of the practice. At most, opinions have offered, as if it
solved something, the observation that the Court has never felt its
power confined to the intended meaning of the Constitution. True enough,
but a long habit of abuse of authority does not make the abuse
legitimate. That is particularly so when the representative branches of
government have no effective way of resisting the Court's
depredations.
Viewing the carnage created by the Court, George Will referred to the
Justices as "our robed masters." When the VMI decision came down, my
wife said the Justices were behaving like a "band of outlaws." Neither
of those appellations is in the least bit extreme. The Justices are our
masters in a way that no President, Congressman, governor, or other
elected official is. They order our lives and we have no recourse, no
means of resisting, no means of altering their ukases. They are indeed
robed masters. But "band of outlaws"? An outlaw is a person who coerces
others without warrant in law. That is precisely what a majority of the
present Supreme Court does. That is, given the opportunity, what the
Supreme Court has always done.
The astonishing thing is that anybody is surprised at this. Without
realizing quite what they were doing, generations of Americans have
accorded all courts, and most especially the Supreme Court, unchecked
power. We ought to have known what would inevitably happen. Lord Acton's
famous aphorism about power corrupting turns out to be right: Given
unchecked power, most human beings, even those in robes, will abuse that
power.
Only a change in our institutional arrangements can halt the
transformation of our society and culture by judges. Decisions of courts
might be made subject to modification or reversal by majority vote of
the Senate and the House of Representatives. Alternatively, courts might
be deprived of the power of constitutional review. Either of those
solutions would require a constitutional amendment. Perhaps an elected
official will one day simply refuse to comply with a Supreme Court
decision.
That suggestion will be regarded as shocking, but it should not be. To
the objection that a rejection of a court's authority would be civil
disobedience, the answer is that a court that issues orders without
authority engages in an equally dangerous form of civil disobedience.
The Taney Court that decided Dred Scott might well have
decided, if the issue had been presented to it, that the South had a
constitutional right to secede. Would Lincoln have been wrong to defy
the Court's order and continue the Civil War? Some members of the
Supreme Court were edging towards judging the constitutionality of the
war in Vietnam. Surely, we do not want the Court to control every major
decision and leave only the minutiae for democratic government.
The truth, however, is that I must end on a pessimistic note. The Court
will not be reformed by persuasion or by changes in its membership. But
the public appears supine, willing to watch democracy slip away. Can
public apathy ratify what the Court is doing? Not in our constitutional
tradition, it can't. If a real constitutional right of one person is
being violated with the unanimous approval of the rest of the United
States, we have always held that the right must be vindicated
regardless. Under our Constitution, each of us has a right to
representative government and no amount or length of majority inertia
can legitimate what the Court is doing to that right.
Robert H. Bork is the John M. Olin Scholar in Legal Studies at the
American Enterprise Institute and author of The Tempting of
America: The Political Seduction of the Law. His latest book is
Slouching Towards Gomorrah: Modern Liberalism and American
Decline (Regan Books/HarperCollins).
If the Court does not claim to act merely in its own name, but for the
common good and the rule of law, how then should citizens regard the
effort to link abortion with the legitimacy of the Court itself and
thus, it would seem, with the legitimacy of our current political
regime? We could put this in a different way by asking whether the
Court-in laying down rules without authority to do so and then asking
for obedience in the name of the common good-has acted ultra
vires, beyond its constitutionally assigned powers. If so, its
commands are not legitimate. The rule of law prohibits reallocation of
shares of authority without the consent of the governed. Since the
political common good depends on no branch of government taking more
than its share of authority, obedience should not be given to an act
that violates the foundation of the rule of law.
So put, we have only stated a principle. Does it apply to the actions of
this Court? It seems to me that the situation is ambiguous and admits no
clear answer. There is no doubt but we live today under an altered
constitutional regime, where the rules are no longer supplied by a
written document but by federal courts defining the powers of government
ad hoc, through their own case law. This profound change from our
previous order of government is often hidden by political and judicial
rhetoric that gives honor to and even cites the written Constitution;
yet, in contemporary theory and in practice, the document is really an
authoritative occasion for, rather than a norm of, judicial
interpretation. The changes have been further obscured by the fact that
the new regime was not ratified by amendment or constitutional
convention.
But this profound and confusing change does not necessarily make the new
constitutional order illegitimate-at least not in the sense we are
exploring here. It is plausible to argue that this new regime evolved
over time with the tacit consent of the governed. Operationally
speaking, every sector of government has acquiesced in the Court's
understanding of its own powers and the powers of rival authorities.
Though the elected representatives of the people may complain about
particular judicial rulings and try to influence those rulings through
judicial appointments and party platforms, none challenge the authority
of the ruling principle itself. Our elected representatives do not
merely comply with, but obey, the Court's understanding of the
constitutional order, and they have tendered obedience for fifty years.
Thus, when the Court in Casey asks that its case law be given
the obedience due to the Constitution, and when it insists that, above
all, it must remain loyal to its own recently established precedents, it
makes a reasonable request within the context of the new constitutional
regime. In this new regime, judicial interpretation rules the text,
according to the Court's perception of the common good and the changing
needs of the polity. It can be pointed out that this is a reckless kind
of polity-allowing the Court to define the nature and scope of political
power on an ad hoc basis, without benefit of the debates of a
legislative assembly or a constitutional convention, and without the
contest of facts typical of an ordinary trial court. One would be very
surprised indeed were it not to engender great injustices. For all of
that, however, the Court does not necessarily act ultra vires.
But the issue of legitimacy can be examined from another point of view.
Citizens can have a duty not to obey a law if it seriously injures the
common good. And were such laws propounded as essential features of the
constitutional order itself-which is to say, propounded as laws
governing the making of any other laws-then we could reasonably ask
about the legitimacy of that regime. Bearing in mind that we are
speaking not of isolated statutes, but of authoritative renderings of
the fundamental law, such laws would be laws (1) that deny protection to
the weak and the vulnerable, especially in matters of life and death,
and (2) that systematically remove the legal and political ability of
the people to redress the situation. A polity that creates and upholds
such laws is unworthy of loyalty.
The first thing to realize about our new regime is that the abortion
right is not a unique or isolated feature of contemporary jurisprudence.
The Court's own case law shows that in order to maintain the abortion
right at the level of fundamental law, many other sectors of the states'
legal order, at both statutory and common law, need to be altered:
family law, marriage law, laws regulating the medical profession, and,
as we now see with the recent circuit court decisions, criminal laws
prohibiting private use of lethal force. The principle of Casey
cannot leave the other institutions of the polity unaffected.
Moreover, the Court's own case law shows that it is impossible to
disempower political opponents of abortion without going on to
disempower them politically on other issues as well. What is one's place
in a political regime that regards abortion as defining of the
constitutional covenant, that expands the principle to other
institutions of both private and public law, and that politically
disempowers opponents?
Three decisions reached by federal courts this past spring reveal a
pattern of fact that will allow us to take a broader view of the
situation. These decisions exemplify both the inherently expansive
nature of the new regime's abortion jurisprudence as well as its
disempowerment of political opponents.
By statewide referendum in 1991, voters in the state of Washington had
reaffirmed the provision of the criminal code that outlawed persons in
its jurisdiction from "knowingly causing or aiding other persons in
ending their lives." On March 6, 1996, the Ninth Circuit Court of
Appeals ruled in Compassion in Dying v. Washington that the
state of Washington is constitutionally powerless to prohibit physicians
(its own licensees) from using lethal force to assist suicides. Seizing
upon the infamous dictum of the abortion decision in Casey -"At
the heart of liberty is the right to define one's own concept of
existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human
life"-Judge Stephen Reinhardt not only posited a "right to die," but
also deemed the state's legislative motive cruel: "Not only is the
state's interest in preventing such individuals from hastening their
deaths of comparatively little weight, but its insistence on frustrating
their wishes seems cruel indeed."
Meanwhile, in New York, the Second Circuit Court of Appeals ruled in
Quill v. Vacco that while there is no "historic" right to die,
the state of New York violates the equal protection clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment with its prohibition of assisting suicide. By
permitting patients to refuse treatment at the end of life, but not
allowing physician-assisted suicide, the state unfairly treats similarly
situated persons. The court brushed aside the distinction between
letting die and killing. Although it was claimed in the press that the
Second Circuit's opinion was more moderate because it did not posit a
"right to die," both decisions reach the same result from the same
principle.
Not surprisingly, in New York that principle was also the dictum in
Casey. Judge Miner, writing for the majority in the Second
Circuit, asked: "What concern prompts the state to interfere with a
mentally competent patient's 'right to define [his] own concept of
existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human
life,' when the patient seeks to have drugs prescribed to end life
during the final stages of a terminal illness?" Miner answers, "None."
In other words, given two patients, each of whom can define the meaning
of the universe, the state of New York violates equal protection when it
allows the one to "define" himself by having treatment withdrawn while
it forbids the other to "define" himself by requesting that a physician
assist his suicide.
The third decision concerned a 1992 statewide referendum in which the
voters in Colorado adopted an amendment, known as Amendment 2, to their
constitution prohibiting laws that make homosexual orientation, conduct,
and relationships the bases of special entitlements to minority status,
quota preferences, and claims to discrimination. On May 20, 1996, in
Romer v. Evans, the Supreme Court ruled that the amendment is
totally without a rational basis, and is "born of animosity toward the
class of persons affected." The Court declined to say whether its
decision silently overturns Bowers v. Hardwick (1986), which
upheld the state of Georgia's anti-sodomy law. Yet if Colorado's
amendment has no basis other than animosity toward homosexuals, it is
difficult to understand what rational grounds might exist for anti-
sodomy laws, or, for that matter, laws restricting marriage to man and
woman.
These decisions have two things in common. First, they expand individual
liberty against traditional morals legislation. And second, they impugn
the motives of legislators, which the Ninth Circuit found "cruel" and
the Supreme Court found hateful. This is the pattern that we need to
notice if we are to understand the legal and political mind of the new
regime. This pattern did not begin, however, with the decisions of this
past spring.
Earlier in the century the Court aggressively protected individual
rights of contract against the democratic process in the states. But
after World War II, the Court began to insert itself into what James
Madison called the "internal" objects of state governments, particularly
the culture-forming institutions, including education, religion,
marriage, and government's domestic control over matters of life and
death. Reasoning that the people do not wish these things to be left to
the ordinary legislative process, the Court incrementally created
individual rights as immunities from the political ordering of these
"internal" objects.
The Court's religion jurisprudence was especially important, and indeed
was a kind of seedbed for the new regime. In 1947, the Court ruled that
the establishment clause must be applied against the states, and that no
establishment means no "promotion" of religion. In 1948, John Courtney
Murray called the new religion jurisprudence "rigid, ruthless,
sweeping," and insisted that the Court's doctrine "cannot be approved by
the civic conscience" (in an essay first printed in First Things,
October 1992). Murray was correct about the sweeping nature of the new
doctrine; over the course of twenty years, religion was removed, bit by
bit, from the civic order of state polities. Murray, however, did not
live to see the next step. In 1971, nonestablishment came to mean that
legislation could have no religious "purposes," even when the immediate
matter and effect of the legislation is secular. Justice O'Connor would
later add that such secular purposes must even be "sincere."
Thus, the Court prohibited public events which had been practiced in
every jurisdiction since the founding of the nation. Then, to sustain
its reasoning in the face of new litigation, the Court found itself
having to bring ever new objects under its scrutiny, such as moments of
silence and abstinence education. Indeed, Justice Kennedy recently has
gone so far as to maintain that the belief that "there is an ethic and a
morality which transcend human invention" is itself religious.
Ultimately, the Court had to interrogate the subjective motivations of
legislators in order to detect the presence or absence of religion.
In a separate line of jurisprudence, the Court moved on to issues of
sex, marriage, and abortion. In hindsight, we see that the new lifestyle
rights were inherently expansive. In Griswold v. Connecticut
(1965), the new right of privacy was meant to protect marriage, and
was justified by reference to the "traditions and conscience of the
people." In Eisenstadt (1972), however, the privacy right was
expanded to cover any reproductive decision made by individuals. In
Roe (1973), it included elective abortion. In Carey
(1977), it included the right of teenagers to have access to
contraceptives. In Casey, it mushroomed into an all-purpose
right to define the meaning of the universe. The circuit courts now
insist that it includes the liberty to contract a physician to assist
one's death. What began as a judicial effort to stretch the Constitution
to make it better reflect the "traditions and conscience of the people"
quickly became the opposite-it became a reason for constitutionally
invaliding those very traditions as the ground for public policies and
laws.
This line of jurisprudence, for a time, steered clear of the
motivational analysis used in religion cases. To be sure, the issue of
religious motivations would, from time to time, emerge in a concurring
or dissenting opinion, when members of the Court would speculate that
state governments have no authentic secular purpose for laws restricting
sexual conduct.
These two lines of jurisprudence have begun to coalesce. Judge Reinhardt
of the Ninth Circuit acknowledges that judicial acceptance of physician-
assisted suicide would cause "great distress" to people "with strong
moral or religious convictions." The "or" is interesting, especially in
the light of Justice Kennedy's virtual equation of religion with any
ethics thought to "transcend human invention." Reinhardt warns, "They
are not free, however, to force their views, their religious
convictions, or their philosophies on all the other members of a
democratic society, and to compel those whose values differ with theirs
to die painful, protracted, and agonizing deaths." Laws prohibiting
physician-assisted suicide, he concludes, do "injury" to some citizens
for no other reason than "to satisfy the moral or religious precepts of
a portion of the population." On this view, legislation informed by
religion or by traditional morality expresses a malicious
desire by some citizens to apply power against other citizens.
In this light, we can begin to understand the Court's decision in the
case of Colorado's Amendment 2. Although in Romer v. Evans
Justice Kennedy does not venture an opinion about the religious nature
of animus against homosexuals, his decision depends heavily upon the
attribution of motives. "Laws of the kind now before us," he writes,
"raise the inevitable inference that the disadvantage imposed is born of
animosity toward the class of persons affected." "If the constitutional
conception of 'equal protection of the laws' means anything," he
continues, "it must at the very least mean that a bare . . . desire to
harm a politically unpopular group cannot constitute a legitimate
governmental interest." In other words, individual liberty is defined
not merely by the kind of act or decision that one is free to engage,
but by immunity from a certain kind of motive or purpose on the part of
the legislator.
This analysis of animus has been linked to equal protection before. In
Bray v. Alexandria Women's Clinic (1993), the Court examined
whether anti-abortion demonstrators could be held liable-under the Ku
Klux Klan act of 1871 (amended in 1985)-of conspiring to deprive women
of the equal protection of the laws by depriving women seeking abortions
of their right to interstate travel. The Bray case is unlike
Romer in dealing with private citizens' animus against a class.
The two can be seen together, however, insofar as the definition of
discriminatory purpose holds for both public or private agents.
Discriminatory purpose, as defined in Bray, implies that the
agent selects or reaffirms a particular course of action in part
"because of" and not merely "in spite of" its adverse effects upon an
identifiable group.
In Bray, it was proposed that women qualify as precisely such
an "identifiable group." Justice O'Connor reasoned that the law must
reach "conspiracies whose motivation is directly related to
characteristics unique" to women. These characteristics are defined as
"their ability to become pregnant and by their ability to terminate
their pregnancies." For his part, Justice Stevens wrote, "When such an
animus defends itself as opposition to conduct that a given class
engages in exclusively or predominantly, we can readily unmask it as the
intent to discriminate against the class itself."
The proposition that pro-life demonstrators are liable for such
discrimination was defeated in Bray by a single vote-Justice
White was still on the bench. For our purpose, however, it is important
to note the strong analogy to what the Court now accuses Coloradans of
doing in adopting Amendment 2. When Justice Kennedy asserts that there
is no rational basis for the amendment, and that the "inevitable
inference" is that the action is "born of animosity toward the class of
persons affected," he is saying, in judicial terms of art, that the
amendment was adopted "because of" and not merely "in spite of" its
adverse effects upon an identifiable group. It is true, of course, that
women have a federal right to have abortions, while homosexuals do not
(as yet) have a federal right to perform acts of sodomy. But the animus
analysis reaches the same result, for a class is allegedly picked out
and bullied in violation of the equal protection clause; whether the
class is entitled to special judicial protection doesn't matter if the
legislators or voters can be ascertained to have a suspect motive.
In sum, the political ability of the people to address legislatively
common concerns in the terms of traditional morality must pass through a
gauntlet of judge-made law in this new regime. If not disqualified on
grounds of religion, legislation and other forms of public business may
be disqualified on grounds of insufficiently "secular" motivation. And
if not knocked down for that reason, it may be disqualified for failure
to comport with what Gerard Bradley has called the "mega-right" of self-
mystery definition posited in Casey (a right that now moves by
analogy into physician-assisted suicide). And if not disqualified
because of that, then it may be disqualified on grounds of motive to do
injury, to discriminate, or to deny to persons equal protection of the
laws.
These disqualifiers have been used alone and in concert to place public
expressions of traditional morality outside the new political order. In
fact, the Court may not need to invent a constitutionally protected
right to die or to commit sodomy. Its current repertoire of
nullification tests and devices are already sufficient to knock down
prohibitory legislation on religious and equal protection grounds.
While it allows individuals to be self-governing, the federal
judiciary's new constitutional order radically undercuts their ability
to be self-governing in the political sense of the term. It excludes
from the political process the objects of mutual deliberation that make
political order desirable, indeed even possible. Desirable, because the
culture-forming institutions of society cannot be sustained without
common effort; there would be no need for politics were there not some
important goods that require the deliberation, direction, and authority
of the community. Possible, because once private individuals are allowed
rights to use lethal force for vindicating justice in their own cause
(as in abortion or euthanasia), it is difficult to see how even the most
rudimentary foundations of the older political society-those that
reserve the use of lethal force to public authority-still remain.
The new constitutional regime is a very bad regime. It withdraws
protection from the weak and vulnerable, allowing the strong to define
the status and rights of the weak; it privatizes matters which, in any
legitimate political order, must be public in nature; it sets
innumerable roadblocks to the rectification of the problem through
mutual deliberation of citizens in legislative assemblies; and it has
made what used to be its most loyal citizens-religious believers-enemies
of the common good whenever their convictions touch upon public things.
In 1994, the Court not only allowed the Racketeer Influenced and Corrupt
Organizations (RICO) statutes to be applied against anti-abortion
demonstrators, putting them in the same category with mobsters, but also
allowed to stand a Florida law restricting the speech of pro-life, but
not pro-choice, demonstrators in the vicinity of abortion clinics.
Unless the new constitutional order is profoundly reformed, citizens of
rightly formed conscience will find themselves in a crisis. Insofar as
private citizens have given tacit consent to the new regime, and thus
allowed it to speak in their name, they face an unavoidable moral
crisis. But the crisis falls even more immediately and heavily upon
public officials, for the new regime orders them to do what they ought
not to do, and not to do what they ought to do. They are ordered not to
regard the unborn as having moral rights, and not to take those steps
otherwise available to their offices to protect and remedy the
injustices against that class of persons. Soon, the same will be true
with respect to the dying and infirm. Moreover, legislative, executive,
and judicial officers in the states are ordered by the Court to prevent
the application of laws and policies of citizens on no other ground than
the citizen's moral or religious motivations.
It is late in the day, and our options have dwindled. Either right-
minded citizens will have to disobey orders or perhaps relinquish
offices of public authority, or the new constitutional rulers will have
to be challenged and reformed. The first option leads inevitably either
to withdrawal from politics or to civil disobedience. Since there is
still a window of opportunity with regard to the second option, it would
seem to be the responsible course. In order to adopt it, we must take
three steps.
First, the people through their elected officials must withdraw whatever
tacit consent has been given to the new constitutional order. Because
the new regime was not erected by any ordinary process of amendment,
referendum, or ratification, in principle the people still may alter it
through their elected representatives. Perhaps the U.S. Congress will be
able to invoke its powers under section five of the Fourteenth
Amendment; perhaps Congress can use its powers under Article III to
alter the Court's appellate jurisdiction. How this might be done must
urgently be studied by those having experience and expertise in the
actual institutions of government.
Second, issues like abortion, euthanasia, and gay marriage should not be
treated as isolated from the broader constitutional crisis. Those who
would try to play within the game imposed by the Court, in the hope of
incrementally improving the situation issue-by-issue, actually deepen
rather than mitigate the authority of the new order. Indeed, it tends to
confirm the suspicion that citizens who hold conservative opinions about
morals and religion lurch from issue to issue, trying to use the public
order merely to win a point, if not to punish those who believe
otherwise. Particular issues therefore need to be advanced for the
purpose of prompting a constitutional crisis; and prompting the
constitutional crisis is the responsible thing to do.
Third, of all the features of the new regime, the one that must be
tackled first is the Court's motivational analysis, which first emerged
in connection with religion, but which now spreads to other matters of
legislation informed by substantive moral purposes. In effect, the Court
makes it impossible to have anything other than a procedural common good
as a motive or purpose for political activity. There is a real
possibility that the moral and religious motivations of some citizens
will become not only actionable at public law, through constitutional
suits challenging legislation informed by such motives, but also
actionable at private law. Unless the elected representatives of the
people can compel the Court to refrain from invalidating political
activity merely on the basis of the citizens' moral or religious
motivation, the task of reform is blocked. Should that continue, the
option remaining to right reason is the one traditionally used against
despotic rule: civil disobedience.
No more than a fortnight after the decision was handed down in Romer
v. Evans, the same professor was in print, in the New
Republic, not only aware of the connection, but quite emphatic now
in his opinion: Romer v. Evans would in fact call into question
the authority of a state in refusing to honor gay marriages. And indeed,
as he suggested, it would call into question the power of the Congress
to act now, with the Defense of Marriage Act, in seeking merely to
preserve, for the states, their freedom to refuse.
That Romer should have any bearing of this kind on the law of
marriage is still barely understood even by people who make their living
by following public affairs. That the decision could have vast,
unsettling effects on our law-that it could be used as a powerful lever
in changing the professions, the universities, and the cast of our
private lives-is well beyond the imagining of a public that does not
spend its days absorbed in the life of the courts. And of course the
media have taken care to shelter the public from any account in these
matters that may be too precise or jolting for the public to hear.
There should be, by now, nothing startling in this pattern, for it has
marked the ways of our courts and our politics over the past thirty
years. The judges form a virtual concert to advance the interests of gay
rights and other parts of the liberal agenda, and those who would resist
these initiatives, even with the most modest measures, are branded as
the aggressors and the zealots. Whether the issue has been abortion, or
euthanasia, or "gay rights," the courts have taken steps that were
noticeable even at the time as novel and portentous. But these moves
seemed to have struck no chord, no moral or religious nerve, running
through the broad public. All of which must make us wonder whether we
are indeed in post-Christian or post-religious America. But if these
events have not set off alarms, it is even less likely that people would
be sensitive to that subtler shift of power that runs to the root of the
American regime itself: In one issue after another touching the moral
ground of our common life, the power to legislate has been withdrawn
from the people themselves, or the "consent of the governed," and
transferred by the judges to their own hands. And on this point, there
has been no example more striking than the recent run of cases on "gay
rights."
In November 1992, the voters of Colorado, in a referendum, foreclosed to
legislatures at all levels the authority to treat gays and lesbians on
the same plane as groups that have suffered discrimination based on
race, religion, and gender. In effect, the amendment to their
constitution ("Amendment 2") would have removed from legislatures the
authority to pass statutes that barred discriminations based on "sexual
orientation." Those statutes provided a club for the law in meting out
public humiliations for people who hold moral and religious objections
to homosexuality. In one telling case, the wife of a shopowner in
Boulder, Colorado had given a pamphlet on homosexuality to a gay
employee. For that offense, she was charged under the local ordinance on
gay rights, and compelled to enter a program of compulsory
counseling.
We will hear, no doubt, many different accounts of Amendment 2 in
Colorado, but I would offer this construction: The Amendment merely
sought to preserve for people, in their private settings, the freedom to
honor their own moral understandings on the matter of homosexuality. The
Amendment licensed no criminal prosecutions directed at gays or
lesbians, and it withdrew from homosexuals no protections of the law.
Still, the Court overturned this move by the people of Colorado, acting
in their sovereign capacity, to shape their fundamental law. Ten years
earlier, in Bowers v. Hardwick, the Court had upheld the power
of a state to make sodomy a crime; but now, as Justice Scalia pointed
out, the Court was willing to strike down a law merely for "disfavoring
homosexual conduct." And in the sweep of its judgment, the Court
produced a decision that could be read by activists among the judges to
encompass this principle: that it would now be immanently suspect on
constitutional grounds to plant, anywhere in the laws, a policy that
casts an adverse judgment on homosexuality, or accords to homosexuality
a lesser standing or legitimacy than the sexuality "imprinted in our
natures." Armed with this decision, judges throughout the country would
be able to tie up, or overturn, any statute in a state that refused to
recognize gay marriage.
During the hearings on the Defense of Marriage Act, Representative Pat
Schroeder (D-Col.) declared that the issue of gay marriage involved
simply our willingness to honor, with equal respect, the love we
encounter in all couples. And yet, as others were quick to point out, no
one doubts the love of men for men, or women for women, just as no one
doubts that there may be abiding relations of love between brothers and
sisters, or grandparents and grandchildren. But those loves cannot be
diminished as loves because they are not attended by penetration or
expressed in marriage. Marriage is not needed to mark the presence of
love, but a marriage marks something matchless in a framework for the
begetting and nurturance of children. It means that a child enters the
world in a framework of lawfulness, with parents who are committed to
her care and nurturance for the same reason that they are committed to
each other.
But that is to say there is a connection, long understood, between
marriage and what may be called the "natural teleology of the body"-the
inescapable fact that only two people, not three, only a man and a
woman, can beget a child. As Michael Uhlmann has remarked, it becomes
impossible finally to talk about marriage without using that "N-word,"
nature, and without talking about the sexuality imprinted in our
"gendered" existence: "Male and female created He them." There is a
purpose plainly marked in the fact that we are born man and woman, and
it was once understood that this purpose found its expression in
marriage as a blending of nature and law. If marriage were entirely a
matter of law, then the positive law could prescribe virtually anything
as a marriage: Brothers then might marry sisters-or brothers; they might
even marry their household pets. Or, they might marry more than one
person. If marriage is detached from that "natural teleology of the
body," on what ground of principle could the law rule out the people who
profess that their own love is not confined to a coupling of two, but
woven together in a larger ensemble of three or four?
When this question was posed in the hearings on the Defense of Marriage
Act, it produced, among the defenders of gay marriage, a show of
bafflement. Yet, the people who were inclined to dismiss the matter of
polygamy were treating with a certain nonchalance something that
deserved to be treated with far more caution and sobriety. For many
years, there have been centers of polygamy in southern Utah and northern
Arizona that have proven intractable. Some telling commentary was
offered by Paul Van Dam, the Attorney General of Utah, in 1990:
For my own part, I would credit the avowals made by gay spokesmen like
Barney Frank and Andrew Sullivan that they do not have the remotest
interest in promoting polygamy, or in weakening the laws that sustain
families. But their argument runs beyond their intentions. The arguments
for gay marriage must in fact put into place the premises that make it
untenable for the law to hold back from the acceptance of polygamy. And
one thing may be attributed to the gay activists quite accurately and
fairly: they have the most profound interest, rooted in the logic of
their doctrine, in discrediting the notion that marriage finds its
defining ground in nature. For that reason, we can count on the fact
that there will be someone, somewhere, ready to press this issue by
raising a challenge in the court and testing the limits even further.
In a widely noticed essay in 1991 the lawyer-activist Nan Hunter argued,
with an unsettling directness, that "the impact of [gay and lesbian
marriage] will be to dismantle the legal structure of gender in every
marriage." For this arrangement, she said, has "the potential to expose
and denaturalize the historical construction of gender at the heart of
marriage." For several years, Ms. Hunter was the director of the AIDS
Project and the Lesbian and Gay Rights Project for the American Civil
Liberties Union. With these credentials, and these published sentiments,
she was eminently suited to her appointment, in 1993, as the "deputy
general counsel/legal counsel" in the Department of Health and Human
Services under the Clinton Administration. She is, in other words, one
of the most highly placed lawyers within the government likely to be
consulted for an official judgment on matters relating to "the family."
And she is in a position, of course, to stoke the engines of
litigation.
For what drives the litigation for gay rights is the need to have the
gay life recognized and confirmed in principle in every setting in which
the issue may arise. Gay activists seem to understand that their
interests will not be secured as long as there persists in the public a
residual moral sense that there is something about homosexuality that is
not quite right. Hence, the need to seek more and more occasions for
inducing the public first to tolerate, and then, in small steps, to
endorse or approve. And now, with Romer v. Evans, the Court has
handed the activists a powerful new device for advancing the movement
ever further.
The reach of this device becomes ever clearer when we recall that the
Court was not faced, in Romer, with an attempt to stir up
prosecutions or withdraw the protections of the law from gays and
lesbians. Colorado had already repealed its laws on sodomy. With
Amendment 2, the people of Colorado had decided simply to withhold
endorsement or favoritism: The coercions of the law would not be used to
punish those people who bore moral objections to homosexuality. And yet,
this perspective, reflected in the law, was characterized by the Court
now as an "animus," a form of blind prejudice that could not justify
itself in the name of any rational purpose. As Scalia noted, his
colleagues were now "disparaging as bigotry adherence to traditional
attitudes," rooted in religious teaching. In a stroke then-and without
the need to marshal any reasons-the Court could pronounce the
traditional moral teaching of Judaism and Christianity as empty,
irrational, unjustified.
Justice Scalia has found his own, distinct touch as a jurist in offering
the concrete example that illuminates the jural landscape; and in this
case, he marked out with a chilling precision the path that leads out
from Romer. Scalia noted that the Association of American Law
Schools requires its members to extract, from the firms interviewing
their students, an "assurance of the employer's willingness" to hire
homosexuals. If an interviewer harbors traditional moral views on
homosexuality, his firm could be in violation of the rule established by
the Association of Law Schools. We can expect, of course, that rules of
this kind will quickly make their way into the bar associations, as well
as other groups of professionals. Will there not be an incentive then
for the law firms to gauge whether any senior partners-or even young
associates-hold views that may put the firm at odds with these
regulations? And the incentives will not emanate simply from the
conventions of the law schools. After all, the Supreme Court itself has
now declared that a moral objection to homosexuality is indefensible, a
distillation of an unreasoned prejudice. If a young, gay associate is
denied standing as a partner, could it not be claimed that the climate
in the firm was poisoned at the outset, that it was set in a
discriminatory cast by the presence of senior partners who bore moral
reservations about homosexuality?
And what can be said in this respect for law firms could be said even
more forcefully about colleges and universities. Given the litigious
experience these days in the academy, we can virtually count on the fact
that such grievances will be filed. What if a member of an academic
department has simply done what I have done-given public testimony, or
published a moral judgment on gay marriage? Might that not supply prima
facie grounds for a grievance later in a case involving the tenure of a
young professor who was gay or lesbian? Would it not be argued that the
situation was at least biased, or tilted, at the outset by the presence
of that member of the faculty? Can we expect, then, certain pressures to
separate those members of the faculty from decisions on tenure and
hiring? And might it finally be best to remove the problem at the root
simply by avoiding the hiring of people who bear these religious and
moral sentiments, which the Supreme Court has now declared to be
prejudicial? In sum, the Court has fashioned, in Romer v.
Evans, a powerful new instrument for blocking from the academy and
the professions people who are "overly serious" about their religion-
which is to say, people who take seriously the traditional moral
teachings of Christianity and Judaism.
Through a series of small steps there is produced, over time, a dramatic
change. And now we find ourselves at the threshold of a situation in
which a serious Catholic, in a law firm, can be seen as a source of
liability, and may need to be quarantined. But the oddity is produced by
the same trend of affairs that stamps the Christian Coalition, or the
religious in politics, as aggressors. The question goes strangely
unasked as to what it was that "politicized" these groups in the first
place and brought them into politics. During the controversy over gay
marriage, the surveys showed about 70 percent of the public opposed to
that novelty. But the same surveys would reveal portions of the public,
comparably large, recoiling from the very people who are inclined to
force a public discussion of the issue. There may be atavistic moral
reflexes, drawn from a Christian past, but they seem readily matched
these days by the reflexes of a newer sensibility that is wary of
anyone who seems "judgmental." Gay marriage may seem wrong, but in the
new scale of things there seems something harsh or tacky about the
people who would argue about the matter in public. And so the political
matrix: The judges advance the interests of gay rights at every turn,
and those who resist them are labeled as the fanatics.
With the same dynamic, the "Christian Right" is tagged with the
responsibility for unsettling our national politics by injecting the
issues of abortion and school prayer. A former adviser to George Bush
asks, earnestly, "Can't we just agree to get this issue (of abortion)
out of national politics?" And he was evidently taken aback when I said,
"Yes, we might make that deal-if by the 'national' government you also
mean the courts." For what was it, after all, that made abortion into a
national issue? It was nothing other than the move of the federal courts
to create a new "constitutional" right to abortion, and, in the name of
that right, to sweep away all of the laws in the separate states that
treated abortion as wrong. The federal courts have shifted the power to
themselves as branches of the federal government, and politicized the
issue at a new level of significance. Yet the people who would resist
them are the ones who are condemned for bringing these divisive issues
into our politics.
But this sense of the matter has taken hold precisely because the media
and the public have absorbed the understanding put forth by the courts
of the rights and wrongs of these matters. If there is something
retrograde, something suspect, about making "discriminations" between
forms of "sexuality," then serious Christians and Jews instantly qualify
as bigots. And the laws that forbid all manner of discrimination seem to
emanate from a disinterested public "ethic," suitably cleansed of any
sectarian shading. The real question for us then is, How did we arrive
at the state of affairs in which this sense of the world has been
absorbed by a vast public in this country, which persists nevertheless
in describing itself mainly as Christian and overwhelmingly as
"religious"? On the question of euthanasia, the judges have quickly
moved from the implausible to the unthinkable, inventing new rationales
for ending the lives of people who were quite plainly alive and not
dying at a decorous speed. On this matter, as on gay rights, there
should have been more than enough to set off alarms for people whose
sensitivities had been shaped by their religious traditions.
We find ourselves asking, then, in a blend of wonderment and outrage:
What would it take in this country-what would have to happen?-before
serious Christians and Jews would recognize, at once, that a critical
line has been crossed? It is one thing to say, as the courts already
have, that the moral precepts of Christianity and Judaism may not supply
the premises of the law in a secular state. It is quite another to say
that people who take those precepts seriously may be enduring targets of
litigation and legal sanction if they have the temerity to voice those
precepts as their own and make them the ground of their acts even in
their private settings.
Perhaps Rousseau, with an edge of madness, had it right: that all of
this simply came along with the ethic of modernity, as it was spread
through the diffusion of the sciences and the arts. "We have all become
doctors, and we have ceased being Christians." Whatever the cause, it
should be plain now that something in the religious sensibility has been
deadened. My friend Russell Hittinger argues, with increasing
persuasiveness, that the courts are making the political regime
unlivable for serious Christians and Jews. To sound that alarm is to
offer the call to political alertness. But the alarm cannot register, it
cannot be felt, among people who have not been affected yet by the
sense, as Christians and Jews, that there is anything taking place that
is especially worth noticing.
A little more than two hundred years into the American experiment,
cultural conservatives stand convicted of unspeakable crimes in the eyes
of most of America's media commentators. The opponents of abortion on
demand, in particular, have felt the whip. Some columnists charge them
with fostering a climate of hatred responsible for the Oklahoma City
bombing and the Michigan militia. One claimed that "the main form of
political terrorism in the United States is perpetuated by right wing
opponents of abortion," while another added that "most anti-abortion
activists" are "religious fanatics who want to impose their version of
God's word on the rest of us."
The Congress seems for the most part to agree with the media, if passage
of the Freedom of Access to Clinics' Entrance Act-the act that narrowed
the First Amendment rights of abortion protestors as an entire class of
citizens-is any indication. And the Supreme Court appears to agree as
well. In Casey v. Planned Parenthood, which enshrined the right
of abortion as a specifically protected Fourteenth Amendment liberty,
the majority lectured pro-lifers for continuing to contest the abortion
issue. They were, in Justice Scalia's words, to "be taught a lesson"-a
lesson the Court forcefully applied in Madsen v. Women's Health
Center, Inc., which created, around abortion clinics, a zone in
which pro-choice advocates were free to demonstrate but even peaceful
abortion protesters were subject to arrest.
Hostility against pro-lifers seems now to have spilled over into a
distrust of any group of citizens seeking to connect public policy with
a transcendent moral order. Writing the decision for the Ninth Circuit
Court of Appeals in Compassion in Dying v. Washington, which
overturned a state ban on euthanasia, Judge Reinhardt slammed the door
on people "with strong moral or religious convictions," as he put it.
"They are not free," he wrote, "to force their views, their religious
convictions, or their philosophies on all the other members of a
democratic society."
That Circuit Court decision has been appealed, but the Supreme Court
itself has expressed similar sentiments. In overturning Colorado's
prohibition of local civil rights statutes based on sexual preference,
the Court in Romer v. Evans effectively branded a bigot any
citizen who considers homosexuality immoral. Writing for the majority,
Justice Kennedy declared, "Laws of the kind before us raise the
inevitable inference that the disadvantage imposed is born of animosity
toward the class of persons affected." Without any supporting testimony
or findings of fact, Justice Kennedy managed to divine that the sponsors
of the referendum and the voters who ratified it must have been
motivated solely by bias.
Kennedy's decision, now the law of the land, forces us to ask a series
of critically important questions: Are citizens-whether Protestants,
Catholics, Jews, or Mormons-who seek to apply transcendent moral values
to public life welcome in political, legal, and cultural debates? Are
citizens free to "impose" such values by referendum or legislative means
in their respective states, or are their efforts inherently
unconstitutional? Does religion (equated by Justice Kennedy in an
earlier case with the belief that "an ethic and a morality which
transcends human invention" exists) have any role to play in
the law?
The answers to these questions have ominous implications for cultural
conservatives. Writing in the Baylor Law Review before the
Romer decision, David Smolin of Samford University Law School
argues that the present Court-rejecting "religiously based" claims as
inherently particularistic-is increasingly dismissing "traditional
theists" as too absolutist to join in public debate in a pluralistic
society. This dismissal of religion (coupled with what he considers the
Court's abandonment of the rule of law) helps explain the "frustrated
religious patriotism" that drives much conservative political action.
With political prospects increasingly out of reach, Smolin predicts
traditional theists with political interests will be forced to abandon
their religious beliefs and accommodate themselves to an amoral,
libertarian regime. The only alternative seems to be an abandonment of
their political interests, becoming what the theologian Stanley Hauerwas
has called "resident aliens" in America-no longer concerned about the
fortunes or misfortunes of a flawed republic, no longer considering this
land their country.
As events at this summer's Republican National Convention in San Diego
show, the putative alliance between the religious right and the
Republican Party offers little solution; and the truth is that grave
dangers exist regardless when the independence of a religious mission is
married to a particular political party's agenda. But utter political
despair, at least, may be premature. Believers may have been told that
their convictions disqualify them from public debate, but the news is
news they've heard before. During the parliamentary struggle to curtail
the British slave trade in the late eighteenth century, Lord Melbourne
sounded much like the U.S. Supreme Court today when he huffed on one
occasion, "Things have come to a pretty pass when religion is allowed to
invade public life." Yet Christian reformers pressed on, rolling back,
one by one, features of the slave trade until it was abolished in 1807
and slavery itself in 1833.
Unfortunately for us, however, events in America may have reached the
point where the only political action believers can take is some kind of
direct, extra-political confrontation of the judicially controlled
regime. Following the logic in Romer, the Supreme Court can in
time strike down state statutes barring polygamy, sodomy, and incest.
Under the Romer logic, I believe, it will easily find no
compelling state interest in confining marriage to a man and a woman,
when the fallout from the case in Hawaii's state courts reaches the
federal level.
A court empowered to judge a statute's constitutionality by that court's
own inference of the animus of the statute's sponsors is a court set
free from any limitations on its power-its power, on the one hand, to
strike down any law enacted with the political aid of believers, and its
power, on the other hand, to move directly against churches and
denominations that display a perceived animus in their teaching toward
certain behavior. The free exercise clause of the First Amendment poses
no obstacle to a judge with any creativity, and-given the demonstrated
animus of the current judicial regime against believers-a showdown
between church and state may be inevitable. This is not
something for which Christians should hope. But it is something for
which they need to prepare.
When considering the relation of church and state, we must remember
first, of course, that in the thirteenth chapter of his letter to the
Romans, Paul has written what must remain for Christians the classic
admonition of obedience to the governing regime. Most scholars and
pastors, however, recognize that this admonition needs to be balanced
with other biblical passages that suggest individuals will at times face
a very clear choice between God and Caesar. The Old Testament prophet
Daniel, rather than violate God's law, was granted permission not to
partake of the king's food-though, we must acknowledge, he took the
minimum resistance necessary, even seeking a pagan official's approval
of an alternative action. His friends Shadrach, Meshach, and Abednego
went further, risking their lives rather than worship pagan idols. In
the New Testament Book of Acts, Peter and John refused to stop preaching
the gospel even as they recognized the state's right to punish them. The
biblical evidence suggests that where a state either demands what God
prohibits or prohibits what God demands, the believer is to obey God and
graciously accept the state's imposed consequences.
Not all Christian thinkers have applied these principles in exactly the
same way. John Calvin, for instance, held a somewhat narrow line,
stressing the responsibility of citizens to fear and honor whatever
ruler is placed over them, even "the most wicked tyrant," a
Nebuchadnezzar or Belshazzar. Though he conceded that disobedience to
the state under certain (biblically identified) circumstances was a
Christian's responsibility-and allowed for lower magistrates to take
issue with rulers on behalf of the people-Calvin remained confident that
God providentially works His will in all sorts of people, good and
bad.
Augustine and Thomas Aquinas, however, saw more circumstances than the
Swiss Reformer where a Christian citizen may need to question or resist
civil authority. Augustine's dictum remains the most famous formulation
of the broader view of a Christian's relation to the state: "An unjust
law is no law at all." Aquinas argued that God's delegation of authority
to civil authorities was linked to the fostering of virtue. When a ruler
meets that test, when his laws and actions are in accord with the
lex divina, and when human law promotes the tranquillitas
ordinis, then human law is just; but if it "runs counter in any way
to the law in us by nature, it is no longer law but a breakdown of law."
Martin Luther King, Jr. cited both these thinkers in defense of civil
disobedience in his Letter from the Birmingham Jail in 1963: "A
just law is man-made code that squares with the moral law of God. Unjust
law is a code that is out of harmony with the moral law." We must
observe, however, that King did not call for general disobedience or
resistance to the state; only the unjust law, he argued in an important
qualification, can be disobeyed.
Among Protestant thinkers, the Scottish Reformer John Knox also saw more
circumstances than Calvin under which civil powers might be disobeyed.
He called on the nobility not simply to resist but to overthrow what he
considered the tyranny of Catholic rule in Scotland. In addition, he
believed that the common people could revolt if the nobility failed in
an effort to bring Reformation to Scotland. A century later, the
Scottish Covenanter Samuel Rutherford penned his classic work Lex
Rex, arguing that the written law stands above the king, and when
the king strays, his actions are unjust and may be resisted, indeed must
be resisted. Rutherford was the inspiration for the twentieth-century
theologian Francis Schaeffer, who claimed in his Christian
Manifesto that "at a certain point there is not only the right, but
the duty, to disobey the state."
The Pauline passage in Romans recognizes two realms: Caesar's and God's.
But Scripture in general, including Paul, recognizes that Caesar rules
under God's authority, with delegated power to achieve certain ends:
justice, domestic tranquillity, the restraint of evil. Christian thought
throughout history has held that any government which perverts these
ends is acting ultra vires, in violation of its delegated
authority. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, the German Lutheran pastor who was
martyred for resisting Hitler, gave what may be the clearest expression
of the principle: "If government persistently and arbitrarily violates
its assigned task, then the divine mandate lapses."
This may be a sort of "preaching to the choir," for it strikes me hardly
anyone would deny that a government can become so corrupt that it is the
positive duty of Christians to resist it. The real questions facing us
are, rather, these: At what point does a government become sufficiently
corrupt that Christians must actively resist it? and, Has the United
States, under its current judicial regime, reached such a point?
Sometimes, to their shame, Christians have not roused themselves to
resist evil government, and sometimes, to their credit, they have. In
1985, after President Marcos invalidated a freely held election in the
Philippines, Christians began gathering in prayer groups. The Roman
Catholic Jaime Cardinal Sin (who emerged as a dominant figure in the
opposition to Marcos) publicly withdrew moral legitimation for a corrupt
regime, holding the state morally accountable before God for its
failings. Shortly thereafter, nuns left their convents, and lay
Christians their homes, to flood the streets where they disarmed the
tanks Marcos had ordered to maintain control.
Protestant churches have acted similarly. In 1934, representatives from
eighteen provincial churches gathered in Barmen to create a "Confessing
Synod" of the German Evangelical Church, declaring ecclesiastical
independence from the Nazi regime. While the convocation was concerned
more with saving the Church than the state, it indirectly questioned the
moral legitimacy of the government and gave impetus to the German
resistance movement. A more obscure but nonetheless interesting case is
the Reformed Presbyterian Church of North America, a small denomination
with roots in western Pennsylvania. Declaring early in American history
that the Constitution was "godless" because it failed to acknowledge the
authority of Jesus Christ, the church up until a generation ago
practiced "political dissent," not allowing members to vote, hold public
office, or take oaths of allegiance to the flag or the Constitution.
The uniqueness of the American experiment provides an opportunity for a
Christian critique of the legitimacy of the current regime. When the
republic was founded, the biblical tradition and the Enlightenment-two
distinct and often antagonistic understandings of the world-seemed to
find a patch of common ground. God's authority was acknowledged ("All
men are endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable rights"), but
sovereignty was vested not in God but in the people who consented to be
so governed. The subsequent experiment in "ordered liberty" was achieved
because, while some saw their liberty secured by God and others by their
status as human beings alone, all agreed to be bound together for the
sake of that liberty.
To use a political term of the time, a "social contract" that included
biblical believers and Enlightenment rationalists was the basis of the
founding of the United States. Whether Christians ought to have agreed
to that contract is an interesting historical and theological question,
but not really of much significance in our present circumstances-for
agree to it Christians did. Our pressing question is rather whether the
successor parties-today's governed populace and their judicial
governors-still recognize the essence of the contract. If one party no
longer does, that party has breached what lawyers call a "condition
precedent": the essential promise by which the other party's agreement
was secured.
If the terms of our contract have in fact been broken, Christian
citizens may be compelled to force the government to return to its
original understanding-as even Enlightenment rationalists have
acknowledged. John Locke, a principal Enlightenment force behind the
theory of a social contract, advocated the right of citizens' resistance
to enforce the terms of the contract. The writings of Thomas Jefferson,
who spoke openly of the necessity of revolution, could also be called
upon for support.
It seems to me, however, that only the Church in some corporate
capacity, not the individual Christian, has the authority to answer the
question of our allegiance to the present regime. While the
fragmentation of American churches poses obstacles to the kind of
ecclesiastical consensus reached in Germany in the 1930s or the
Philippines in the 1980s, some kind of convocation of theologically
orthodox bodies could presumably join to consider the duty of Christians
under the present order. (The statement "Evangelicals and Catholics
Together," published in First Things in May 1994, demonstrates that
joint efforts are possible.) While such a convocation could not claim to
speak with total authority as the Church, it could give voice to a
consensus of opinion among Christians in America.
Only the Church collectively can decide at what point a government
becomes sufficiently corrupt that a believer must resist it. But, with
fear and trembling, I have begun to believe that, however Christians in
America gather to reach their consensus, we are fast approaching this
point. Most orthodox Christians are likely to find it impossible to
support a political regime under which the judiciary-without any
legislative license-sanctions abortion, euthanasia, and homosexual
marriage. Few believers are likely to pledge their allegiance to a
government under which the courts-in the name of "constitutional rights"
they themselves have sole authority to read into the Constitution-can
systematically close off any form of political opposition by declaring
it to betray the "inevitable inference" of animus.
And if, after prayerful deliberation, Christians corporately determine
that our present government has violated its God-given mandate, what
then? After the pattern of the confessing German church, the Church
would first have to separate herself and declare her independence,
disavowing any moral legitimacy indirectly or unofficially provided for
the state in the past. Through her teaching and preaching office, the
Church would need to expose the nature of the state's rebellion against
God-in effect, bringing the state under the transcendent judgment of
God. Though clergy and ecclesiastical officers must refrain from
partisan political activity, as I have cautioned elsewhere, condemning
the taking of innocent lives is not partisan, whether through protesting
abortion clinics or (as the British clergy did in World War II)
denouncing a government for bombing civilian targets.
Churches and religious organizations in this country have already, in
limited circumstances, asserted their independence at some cost. In the
1980s, when New York barred discrimination against the hiring of
practicing homosexuals by private agencies with city contracts, the
Salvation Army, Agudath Israel, and the Catholic archdiocese simply
refused city funds; in the case of the archdiocese, that meant losing
$72 million in funding.
But what if all these actions fail to deter the state? Churches must
then consider a higher level of resistance. In the campaign against
slavery in the nineteenth century, Protestant churches used internal
discipline and external pressure. The revivalist Charles Finney refused
communion to slaveholders. Others organized the Underground Railroad and
rescued fugitive slaves from prison. Many ministers broke the law, were
arrested, and some were imprisoned.
But would even active disobedience be effective against our current
judicial state? When peaceable means and limited civil disobedience
fail-at least according to the Protestant theologians Knox and
Rutherford-revolution can be justified from a Christian viewpoint. While
Knox called for the overthrow of a ruler in the interest of the
Reformation, Rutherford advocated revolt in any instance when a king or
ruler acted contrary to the written law. Apparently, many Christians in
colonial times agreed with Rutherford. After dumping tea in the Boston
harbor, one Boston pastor, Jonathan Mayhew, argued that for a people to
"arise unanimously and resist their prince, even to dethrone him, is not
criminal but a reasonable way of vindicating their liberties and just
rights."
Of course, the same standards Augustine used to evaluate the justice of
a war apply to the justice of a revolution: no other alternative is
feasible; the advantages outweigh the suffering caused; and the evil
employed in the revolution prevents far greater evil. The churches would
have to be convinced that our present government had become totally
opposed to God's purposes and that there was no other solution to
prevent massive evil. And this point, I believe, we have not yet
reached.
Prudence requires greater understanding than most Christians presently
have about the threat that recent and pending court decisions pose. In
Compassion in Dying v. Washington, Ninth Circuit Judge
Reinhardt literally dared the Supreme Court to reverse Hardwick v.
Bowers (the five-to-four decision in 1986 that upheld Georgia's
statute against sodomy). Three of the five justices in the
Hardwick majority have been replaced, and the decision appears
to be, as Judge Reinhardt eagerly pointed out, at odds with the
rationale behind the Casey decision. If Hardwick
falls, the Court may likely require states to recognize homosexual
marriage. Christians therefore would be forced to live under a
government whose actions violate the biblical ordering of social life
and threaten the first institution ordained by God.
Reinhardt's decision in Compassion in Dying v. Washington
itself prohibited states from preventing euthanasia-which, if upheld by
the Supreme Court, means that the medical murder of the sick and elderly
has become our government's national policy. Similarly, President
Clinton's veto of the congressional bill banning the murder of babies
when partially delivered is tantamount to affirmation of infanticide. It
would be hard to imagine that a Christian in good conscience could swear
to uphold the Constitution or laws of a nation that practices the
horrendous offense against God of taking the defenseless lives of the
weakest among us: babies, the elderly, and the sick.
The fervent and ceaseless prayer of every Christian should be that the
discussion of resistance and revolution remains an academic exercise. We
must continue for now to work relentlessly within the democratic
process. Abhorring a confrontation, we should be engaged in a search for
wisdom and a consensus to help us respond to the crisis of the time. Our
discussions about the duty of Christians to the current American
political order must be conducted with care, in a manner that is formal
rather than intuitive, deliberative rather than spontaneous, regulative
rather than pragmatic. Calmness and seriousness of demeanor is necessary
both to prevent the media dismissing us as fanatics and to prevent
individuals from taking matters into their own hands.
And, after all, the Supreme Court may possibly keep faith with the
original contract that brought Christians into the republic; seeing what
it unleashed with Roe and institutionalized with Casey,
it may yet rediscover the principle of judicial restraint.
Politicians may be persuaded of their error in supposing economic
positions more important than moral positions. Perhaps some of our most
vitriolic critics in the media may discover that Christianity has been
historically a far more powerful force for common good than the reverse.
God is sovereign, after all, and He is in the miracle business. And if
the polls are right, believing Protestants and Roman Catholics,
generally socially conservative, represent a viable political majority
in this country.
We dare not at present despair of America and advocate open rebellion.
But we must-slowly, prayerfully, and with great deliberation and serious
debate-prepare ourselves for what the future seems likely to bring under
a regime in which the courts have usurped the democratic process by
reckless exercise of naked power.
Charles W. Colson is Chairman of Prison Fellowship and the 1993
recipient of the Templeton Prize for Progress in Religion. He is the
author of fourteen books and coeditor of Toward a Common Mission:
Evangelicals and Catholics Together (Word).
Why not three?
In his encyclical Evangelium Vitae (1995), Pope John Paul II
reminds us that "fundamentally democracy is a 'system' and as such is a
means and not an end. Its 'moral value' is not automatic, but depends on
conformity to the moral law to which it, like every other form of human
behavior, must be subject." This doctrine of the necessary conformity of
civil law to moral truth long predates the rise of modern democracy. It
is present in both Plato and Aristotle, and was given careful,
systematic expression by St. Thomas Aquinas. It has been a central
feature of the tradition of papal social teaching.
As applied to modern democracy, the idea is that the moral legitimacy of
a law or public policy cannot be established merely by showing that it
was put into place through the workings of democratic institutions. It
is true, as the Pope affirms, that democracy is uniquely valuable
because it embodies more fully than any alternative system the principle
of the fundamental moral equality of citizens. For this reason, the Pope
says that the "almost universal consensus with regard to the value of
democracy . . . is to be considered a positive 'sign of the times,' as
the Church's magisterium has frequently noted." Nevertheless, even a
democratic regime may compromise its legitimacy and forfeit its right to
the allegiance of its citizens.
This happens when the institutions of a democracy are manipulated so
that "'right' ceases to be such, because it is no longer firmly founded
on the inviolable dignity of the person. . . . In this way, democracy,
contradicting its own principles, effectively moves towards a form of
totalitarianism." In such an event, democratic institutions become
mechanisms of injustice and oppression, thus defying the moral law to
which they, like all human institutions and actions, are subject. As
Pope John XXIII wrote in his encyclical Pacem in Terris (1963),
"Any government which refused to recognize human rights, or
acted in violation of them, would not only fail in its duty; its decrees
would be wholly lacking in binding force."
These are no mere sectarian teachings. Belief that laws and the regimes
that make and enforce them must be evaluated by reference to universal
standards of justice is shared by people of different faiths and of no
particular faith. It is the premise of any serious conception of human
rights. And few people who are serious about human rights are naive
enough to believe that democratic institutions can never be used to
violate human rights. Indeed, a central justification for judicial
review of legislation is to provide a check against the possibility that
more democratically responsive institutions of government will disregard
constitutional guarantees and tread upon people's fundamental rights.
One of the saddest lessons of American history, however, is that courts
exercising the power to invalidate legislation as unconstitutional can
themselves trample upon fundamental rights, and, indeed, can do so
precisely in the name of protecting such rights. This happened, for
example, when the Supreme Court of the United States, in a ruling that
helped to precipitate the Civil War, held in Dred Scott v.
Sandford that blacks were noncitizens-and, for all practical
purposes, nonpersons-possessed of no rights that white people must
respect. In our own time, the Supreme Court, in Roe v. Wade,
struck down the abortion laws of all fifty states, effectively wiping
out all legal protection of unborn human beings against being killed
upon the request of their mothers. Most recently, federal courts of
appeal for the Second and Ninth Circuits-the latter court relying
explicitly on the abortion jurisprudence of Roe and its
progeny-have invalidated laws prohibiting physician-assisted suicide in
New York and California.
A familiar and important argument against the "judicial activism" on
display in these cases is that such decisions constitute the judicial
usurpation of legislative authority. This argument highlights the
antidemocratic character of the decisions. It prescinds, however, from
the substance of the moral questions involved-the rightness or wrongness
of slavery or legalized abortion and euthanasia as a matter of public
policy. Justice Antonin Scalia, perhaps the leading exponent of this
criticism, emphasizes the purely procedural quality of the argument by
declaring abortion, for example, to be a matter entirely outside the
purview of constitutional law and, therefore, beyond the jurisdiction of
courts.
In criticizing Roe, Scalia argues that the Constitution,
properly interpreted, leaves the people of the states free to legislate
against abortion. In a noteworthy address at the Gregorian Pontifical
University in Rome, however, he recently declared that by the same
token, "if the people want abortion, the state should permit abortion in
a democracy." While the Justice made clear his own preference for pro-
life public policies, he argued that in itself democracy is neutral as
between competing positions on issues such as abortion and euthanasia.
"I do not know how you can argue on the basis of demo-cratic theory," he
said, "that the government has a moral obligation to do something that
is opposed by the people." Responding to a questioner who raised the
issue of the rights of minorities, Scalia declared that "the whole
theory of democracy, my dear fellow, is that the majority rules; that is
the whole theory of it. You protect minorities only because the majority
determines that there are certain minority positions that deserve
protection."
The Pope's argument in Evangelium Vitae, by contrast,
highlights the sense in which the abandonment of the unborn to abortion
and the infirm to euthanasia betrays the substantive principle of equal
worth and dignity that is the moral linchpin of democracy. Any regime,
including a democratic one, degenerates into what the Pope calls a
"tyrant state" when its law exposes the weakest and most vulnerable
members of the community-those most in need of the law's protection-to
private lethal violence or other forms of oppression. The dark irony of
American constitutional democracy is that our judges-whose special
responsibility it is to preserve the core democratic principle of
equality before the law-are the ones whose edicts have betrayed this
principle. When considered in light of the substantive moral basis of
democratic governance, Roe v. Wade and similar decisions stand
out as "undemocratic" in a far more radical sense than the one Justice
Scalia has in mind.
If the moral law is anything like what Christians and Jews have long
supposed it to be, then there are profoundly important respects in which
the institutions of American democracy-particularly the courts-have made
themselves its enemy. Mary Ann Glendon has observed that the abortion
license manufactured in Roe and upheld in Planned
Parenthood v. Casey is more sweeping than that of any other
democratic nation on the face of the earth. "No other democracy," she
remarks, "is so careless of the value of human life." Predictably, the
legalization of abortion is paving the way to assisted suicide and
euthanasia. The decisions of the Second and Ninth Circuit Courts will
give the Supreme Court an opportunity to declare that the right "to
define one's own concept of existence, of meaning, the universe, and the
mystery of human life," to which it appealed in upholding the abortion
license in Casey, includes the right to kill yourself, to a
physician's assistance in killing yourself, and to someone else's
"substituted judgment" that you should be killed when you are too infirm
to decide for yourself.
What are serious Jews, Christians, and other pro-life citizens to say
about such laws and the institutions that bring them into being? In
Evangelium Vitae, John Paul II teaches that "laws which
authorize and promote abortion and euthanasia are radically opposed not
only to the good of the individual but also to the common good; as such
they are completely lacking in juridical validity." The Pope is not here
making a claim about the technical status of such laws within the legal
systems of the countries that have them. He is, rather, concerned with
their moral force, that is to say, their capacity objectively to bind
the conscience of citizens. "A civil law authorizing abortion or
euthanasia," he declares, "ceases by that very fact to be a true,
morally binding law."
When Evangelium Vitae was issued, the Pope's warning that ours
is becoming a "culture of death" grabbed the headlines-and rightly so.
An equally important aspect of his teaching, however, received less
publicity. This was the Pope's call for all of us to "live the Gospel of
Life." The Pope emphasizes again and again that this is a call to
action. All of us must give witness to the sanctity of human
life, not merely by personally refraining from abortion and euthanasia,
but by working in various spheres-including the political sphere-to
overcome these "crimes against life" and create a new "culture of
life."
For some, this will mean making financial sacrifices to support the pro-
life cause in its various dimensions. For others, it will mean
volunteering to assist in the critical work of pro-life pregnancy
centers and hospices. For still others, it will mean working in the
educational, legal, and political realms to reverse the judicial
decisions and legislative and executive acts that have ushered in the
"culture of death." For all who believe in a God of love, justice, and
mercy, it will mean constant prayer not only for the victims of the
"culture of death," but also for those who are joined in the great
struggle on their behalf, and, indeed, for those misguided souls who, by
political action or by personal involvement in the killing of the unborn
or infirm, have made themselves their oppressors.
To all who work in shaping public policy, the Pope directs a special
plea to make a concern for the health of the family "the basis and
driving force of all social policies." In this vein, he says, it is
essential to resist "the trivialization of sexuality," which is "among
the principal factors which has led to contempt for new life." Moreover,
the Pope calls for greater support for adoption as a true pro-life
alternative to abortion. Here, one is reminded of the profound witness
of Mother Teresa at the National Prayer Breakfast in February of 1994:
"Please do not kill the child. I want the child. Please give me the
child. I am willing to accept any child who would be aborted." Those of
us who would resist the culture of death must join our voices with hers.
For us, and the society we must strive to create, there can be no such
thing as an "unwanted" child.
Does the Pope not, however, call for even more? How are we to understand
his teaching that resistance to the "culture of death" demands
"disobedience" and even "conscientious objection" to unjust laws? Laws
that authorize the killing of the unborn or infirm are permissive in
form. They license and sometimes encourage private killing, but do not
positively command it. (This is what enables supporters of abortion to
describe themselves as "pro-choice." Of course, by this logic, so were
supporters of antebellum laws that permitted slavery, yet required no
one to own slaves or to demand return of fugitive slaves.) Therefore,
disobedience and conscientious objection to such laws must, in most
cases, be indirect. A good example is that of physicians in United
States military hospitals abroad who announced their refusal to perform
elective abortions when President Clinton issued an executive order
lifting the ban on these abortions in such hospitals. Another example is
that of citizens of states which pay for abortions with public funds who
refuse, as a matter of conscience, to remit to state government a
portion of their taxes corresponding to the percentage of the state
budget that goes to abortion funding. Yet another example is that of
nonviolent protestors at abortion clinics who defy unjust restrictions
of their freedom of speech in order to plead the case for the unborn to
women contemplating abortion.
In upholding the abortion license in the Casey decision, a
plurality opinion of Justices Souter, O'Connor, and Kennedy called upon
pro-life Americans to stop their resistance to legalized abortion and
accept "a common mandate rooted in the Constitution." For reasons the
Pope makes clear, this is a proposition that Catholics and other pro-
life Americans cannot accept. The doctrine of the necessary conformity
of civil law to moral truth imposes on conscientious citizens of a
regime that authorizes the killing of the unborn and infirm a clear
obligation of resistance. It is not merely that the claim of these
justices to have found a pro-abortion "mandate" in the Constitution is
manifestly ludicrous. The value of constitutional democracy lies
ultimately in its capacity to serve and secure the common good, which
demands, above all, the protection of fundamental human rights. If the
Constitution really did abandon the vulnerable to private acts of lethal
violence, and, indeed, positively disempowered citizens from working
through the democratic process to correct these injustices, then it
would utterly lack the capacity to bind the consciences of citizens. Our
duty would not be to "accept a common mandate," but to resist.
Has the regime of American democracy forfeited its legitimacy? One way
of avoiding an affirmative answer to this question is to observe that
the judicial decisions at issue are gross misinterpretations of the
Constitution. They are examples of what Justice Byron White, dissenting
in Roe v. Wade, called the "exercise of raw judicial power." At
the same time, however, these decisions have consistently been
acquiesced in by the legislative and executive branches of government.
Congress has not defied the Supreme Court, as it ultimately did in
Dred Scott. And, although not every President has actively
abetted the culture of death-as President Clinton did, for example, in
issuing a series of pro-abortion executive orders and vetoing the
congressional ban on partial-birth abortions-no recent President has
worked steadily to ensure, by judicial appointments and other actions,
that anti-life judicial decisions are reversed.
To say that the worst abuses of human rights have come from the least
democratic branch of government-the judiciary-is true, but of
increasingly questionable relevance to the crisis of democratic
legitimacy brought on by judicial action in the cause of abortion and
euthanasia. In practice, the American scheme of constitutional democracy
invests the courts with ultimate authority to decide what the
Constitution is to mean. Judicial action and appointments can, and
sometimes do, become major issues in national elections. The refusal of
the courts over more than twenty-three years to reverse Roe v.
Wade must, then, be accounted a failure of American democracy.
The judicial movement toward euthanasia makes it plain that the hour is
late. The "culture of death" is well-advanced in our nation. As the Pope
says, "given such a grave situation, we need now more than ever to have
the courage to look the truth in the eye and to call things by their
proper names, without yielding to convenient compromises or to the
temptation of self-deception." Let us, therefore, speak plainly: The
courts, sometimes abetted by, and almost always acquiesced in, federal
and state executives and legislators, have imposed upon the nation
immoral policies that pro-life Americans cannot, in conscience, accept.
Since the legitimacy of institutions of governance-be they democratic or
otherwise-depends ultimately on their capacity and willingness to
preserve and promote the common good by, above all, protecting
fundamental human rights, the failure of the institutions of American
democracy to fulfill their responsibilities has created what is truly a
crisis. People of good will-of whatever religious faith-who are prepared
to consider seriously the Pope's teaching in Evangelium Vitae
cannot now avoid asking themselves, soberly and unblinkingly, whether
our regime is becoming the democratic "tyrant state" about which he
warns.
Robert P. George is Associate Professor of Politics at Princeton
University and author, most recently, of Making Men Moral: Civil
Liberties and Public Morality.
Our Judicial Oligarchy
Robert H. Bork
A Crisis of Legitimacy
Russell Hittinger
Russell Hittinger is the Warren Professor of Catholic Studies and
Research Professor of Law at the University of Tulsa.A Culture Corrupted
Hadley Arkes
Every law enforcement officer in Utah knows
there are tens of thousands of polygamists in the area, and
they are clearly violating the law. Yet if we prosecute
these men and women, we know [from experience] that we will
produce an incredible social disruption. Thousands of
children must be cared for emotionally and otherwise, and
that's a terribly expensive proposition.
In addition, if you go after polygamists for
illegal cohabitation, can you limit such a policy to
polygamists, or do you pursue every couple in this state
that is living together without benefit of a licensed
marriage?
In other words, the authorities are already aware that the principled
grounds of their restrictions have been compromised by the changes in
the climate of opinion that have swept away the moral inhibitions on
couples living together outside of marriage. One state legislator could
remark, with offhandedness, that polygamy just doesn't happen to be a
big issue back in Iowa. But it seemed to elude this earnest man that
polygamy does not happen to be an issue in his state precisely because
the law, for many years, has cast up serious barriers against the
practice. And if those barriers started coming down, do we really think
that our species would be incapable of manifesting once again an
interest in that arrangement?
Hadley Arkes is the Edward Ney Professor of Jurisprudence and American
Institutions at Amherst College and author of The Return of George
Sutherland: Restoring a Jurisprudence of Natural Rights (Princeton
University Press).Kingdoms in Conflict
Charles W. Colson
The Tyrant State
Robert P. George
Abortion and euthanasia are crimes which no
human law can claim to legitimize. There is no obligation in
conscience to obey such laws; instead there is a grave
and clear obligation to oppose them by conscientious
objection.
Plainly, the Pope's teaching is a firm rebuke to those who claim to be
"personally opposed" to abortion and euthanasia but who act to advance
these evils in the public sphere. "In the case of an intrinsically
unjust law, such as a law permitting abortion or euthanasia," the Pope
says, "it is . . . never licit to obey it, or to take part in a
propaganda campaign in favor of such a law, or vote for it." But the
Pope's call for disobedience and conscientious objection goes beyond
even the condemnation of the craven "personally opposed, but pro-choice"
position. His teaching is directed not merely to those who would join
the ranks of Mario Cuomo, Bill Clinton, and Father Robert Drinan, but to
all of us. We are, the Pope says, in the midst of a great conflict
between "the culture of life" and "the culture of death": "We are all
involved and we all share in it, with the inescapable responsibility of
choosing to be unconditionally pro-life."