[ Hoover Award Iran Projects How I Became a Christian Christian Apologetics ]
Professional Ethics without Religion
Dr.
Otto J. Helweg
ABSTRACT:
It seems that writers on professional ethics attempt to dissociate
ethics from religion. There are philosophical reasons why this is not only bad
strategy but fundamentally flawed logically. If each individual does not have
an existential reason for being ethical, all the codes in the world cannot produce
ethical behavior. This paper argues that a theistic presupposition is a sufficient,
if not necessary, condition to supply the existential motivation. Moreover,
professional societies should encourage rather than discourage their members
to integrate their theological inclinations with the appropriate ethical codes.
Though the principles are generally applicable, the paper is written from the
perspective of an engineer.
INTRODUCTION:
The field of ethics can be divided into two parts; first, what ought one to
do?; and second, why should one do what one ought? Ethical literature concentrates,
almost exclusively, on the first question as illustrated by the "Engineering
Ethics" column in The Professional Engineer as well as the various
codes (ASCE, 1962; Baier, 1965; Baum, 1980; Canfield & Bowman, 1954; Flores,
1980; Mantell, 1964; and Mock, 1969). However, most of the ethical code violations
indicate that the problem is "not knowing what to do, but failing to do
what one knows." (Alger, et.al., 1965) Consequently, this study attempts
to redress this imbalance by dealing with the individual's motivation to be
ethical.
BACKGROUND:
Laymen have been frustrated because philosophers do not agree on an ethical
system. That is, philosophers do not have a consistent answer the two questions
raised previously. Some professionals have interpreted this diversity of opinion
as meaning there is no definition (Vesilind, 1988) or no definition is possible.
Such an attitude is understandable for engineers, scientists, and others who
are used to statistical if not mathematical rigor. Nevertheless, two points
may be made; first, disagreement concerning which ethical system is correct
does not mean a correct system does not exist and second, in spite of seeming
confusion, each person must choose the ethical system he or she will follow.
In a sense to not choose is to choose by default.
The first question one encounters when deciding what one ought to do is whether
ethics is normative (prescriptive) or empirical (descriptive). The former would
accept an absolute standard of "good" while the latter would declare
that "good" is relative, such as situational ethics. The following
list of ethical systems will generally fall into one of these two camps.
ETHICAL SYSTEMS:
First in considering what one ought to do, that is, which system of ethics is
right (if any), it is helpful to list the alternatives. Though any taxonomy
is somewhat arbitrary, the one suggested by Holmes (1984) will be followed.
Emotivist Ethics
Ethical emotivism holds that talk about ethics is based on emotion or feelings
and as such has no objective content. For example, the logical positivists would
allow ethical terms to be defined but would deny that emotive words have meaning
because moral judgments are not definitions nor are they empirically verifiable.
The emotive ethicist would not say, "stealing is wrong," but "people
in Memphis feel stealing is not acceptable." Therefore, ethics is subjective
(empirical, descriptive).
In support of this position, most would agree that the subject of ethics is
highly emotional; notwithstanding, how does the emotive ethicists know ethical
terms do not refer to something external to ourselves? To what would they attribute
mankind's universal "judicial instinct" (Carnell, 1957).
Ethical Egoism
This ethical school is similar to utilitarianism (which follows) but ethical
egoism bases "oughtness" on what is best for one's self while utilitarianism
is based on what is best for society. Ethical egoism ranges from crass (destructive)
selfishness to a "benign" selfishness (Scriven, 1966). The former
would base "oughtness" on what ever satisfies one's wants, no matter
how materialistic. Benign selfishness (really unselfishness) argues that seeking
the good of society really maximizes our selfish desires because (among other
things) it promotes a safe environment.
Of course strict selfishness would produce anarchy of the worst sort but unselfish
behavior may, indeed, produce a desirable society. The problem would be convincing
people that unselfishness would, in fact, benefit them more than crass selfishness.
Such a theory would be severely tested when it came time to sacrifice one's
own life for the sake of society. This seems to be the reverse of Adam Smith's
"invisible hand." (Ferguson and Gould, 1975)
Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism, as mentioned above, defines "oughtness" as that which
produces the best for society. This was recently popularized in the movie, "Star
Trek II" in which Mr. Spock said, "the good of the many out weigh
the good of the few." The problem is how to define "the good of the
many." Would it be the dictator in Huxley's, Brave New World, or a similar
totalitarian system?
Again, we have our "oughtness" built on an empirical base. Without
the ability to define the "good of the many" in a normative sense,
our "oughtness" may not only be incorrect, but might not protect individual
rights or minority interests. Moreover, we still have the problem of convincing
people to be unselfish. This has proven to be the Achilles heel of Marxism.
That is, why should I sacrifice now for a future that arrives (if it does) after
I am dead?
Christian Ethics
Rather than define "religious ethics," Holmes chooses to deal with
a subset, Christian ethics. Both religious ethics and Christian ethics are normative
systems that defines "oughtness" in terms of God's laws. Something
is good or right because God says it is.
There are two problems with religious ethics. First, as an argument, it may
be begging the question. One must presuppose a God who has created an ethical
order as well as physical universe. (The failure of the Eastern Religions to
accept this does not have a practical effect at this point.) Second, the various
religions seem to have the same problem philosophers do by disagreeing on what
God's ethical laws are. This second problem is not as severe as it may seem
at first because all religions have remarkable agreement on the basic principles
of ethics. For example, some form of the "golden rule" can be found
in them all. (Hume, 1959)
In spite of these common elements in the ethics of all the major religions,
they (with the exception of Christianity) are built on a legal system which
can easily degenerate into casuistry. The distinctive of Christianity is that
it deals with principles (ie. the "law" of love) rather than individual
commands. Though the operation of love is further defined in Christian writings
(namely the Bible), even here there can be areas of disagreement in the actual
outworkings. For example, some feel serving in the armed forces is wrong while
others believe it is an obligation.
ETHICAL MOTIVATION
The main thrust of this paper resulted because the author has found no reference
dealing with professional ethics that examines the second question of ethics,
"Why should one be ethical?" All the authors address what we ought
to do and few, if any, even acknowledge the existence of the motivation to do
what we ought. Many assume education produces motivation. The weakness of this
assumption is obvious.
The study of economics give insight into motivation. The economic term "goods"
was derived from what is good ethically. The economist assumes that the more
goods, the better; both to society and the individual which (some economists
acknowledge) means that man is basically selfish.
The results of this selfishness can be good or bad behavior (usually the latter
is ignored). The issue is whether individual selfishness is good or bad for
society. Some, calling upon Adam Smith's "invisible hand" say maximizing
individual selfishness also maximizes social utility. However, others cite the
"law of the commons" which says the opposite.
The law of the commons can be illustrated by ten shepherds each having 10 sheep
on a meadow (commons) that can optimally support 100 sheep. One of the shepherds
reasons that adding only one sheep will increase his income by 10% while hardly
effecting the total output of the meadow. Of course the other shepherds quickly
recognizes that unless they do likewise, they will lose out. The result is a
ruined meadow.
The invisible hand might work where there are unlimited resources, but in a
"zero sum game" the law of the commons will prevail. Moreover, Adam
Smith seemed to presume that individuals maximizing their utility (selfishness)
would do so fairly. Even Adam Smith recognized that common goods (water, air,
etc.) and public goods (military service, education, etc.) were exceptions.
It may be further argued that individual selfishness will rarely, if ever, produce
societal well being. In fact, one could argue that it is theoretically and practically
impossible that integrating individual selfishness can somehow produce social
good. Therefore, the problem is to motivate people to be unselfish.
This can be done by external motivation or internal motivation. Our law enforcement
system is designed to supply external motivation and is primarily negative in
that it punishes but does not reward. Society or culture may offer positive
rewards, however.
The weakness with external motivation is the ability of some selfish individuals
to not be caught so those who remain unselfish are like the shepherds on the
meadow who do not react to the one increasing his herd. Also, an unacceptable
burden is placed on the judicial system if a majority of individuals are not
voluntarily "unselfish."
The theist's principal motivation is not to escape "being caught"
but obeying God because in the final judgement, nothing is hid. There is, however,
the problem of people fooling themselves into thinking they are obeying the
divine command but in reality are engaging in casuistry. That is, they seek
"legal ways" to be "illegal."
Christian ethics are based on internal motivation also, but with the difference
that one is to obey the divine command "from the heart" as a result
of having been forgiven, not for any negative or positive reward.
It is patently clear that even Christians, in spite of their internal motivation,
do not always obey the law. This problem stems from the battle between the superego
and the id (Freud,1952). Put in other terms, "we do not do what we want"
(Romans 7:18-24). At least, however, the internal motivation is there which
is a perquisite to conscious ethical behavior.
CONCLUSIONS:
There are three conclusions to draw from the above arguments. First, there are
persuasive arguments that say a theistic presupposition is a prerequisite to
rational internal ethical motivation. Anscombe (1958) supports this by saying,
"...it is not possible to have such a concept unless you believe in God
as lawgiver..." The existence of a final judgement (completely fair with
no hidden evidence) provides a minimum ethical motivation. Further motivation
would be available to those who desire to obey God from gratitude rather than
for reward or punishment. This is not to imply that atheists or non theists
are not ethical, but only that they do not have a rational basis for their motivation.
Second, constructing a normative ethical system (which, by definition, codes
of ethics are) from a relative foundation is a non sequitur. It would seem that
only a normative (prescriptive) ethical system can supply the principles and
standards on which we base our professional codes.
Finally, it is not necessary to agree that a theistic world view is the only
foundation for ethical action or ethical motivation. But, if one concedes that
the individual's theological presuppositions can produce the existential motivation
to "do what one ought," then these presuppositions should at least
be tolerated if not encouraged.
Some professional societies, in particular, the American Society of Civil Engineers,
ASCE, have taken a neutral if not negative stance toward religious groups. For
example, the Christian Engineers have not been allowed to announce their luncheon
meetings in the ASCE conference schedule. Instead, ASCE (and all professional
organizations) should encourage members to integrate their faith as engineers,
scientists, or other professionals with the practice of their profession. It
may well be that this cadre of religious professionals is essential to support
both the codes ("what ought one to do?") and the practice ("doing
what one ought").
Christian Apologetics
Index
Home
page